Evolution Icon Evolution
Intelligent Design Icon Intelligent Design

Revolutionary Biology

922289298_2595face5f_o.jpg

It is not surprising that for thousands of years people thought the Sun and stars revolve around the Earth. We see it with our own eyes every day and night. In 1543, however, Nicolaus Copernicus proposed that the Earth revolves around the Sun and thereby revolutionized our conception of the solar system and the universe. A century and a half later, Isaac Newton proposed laws of motion and gravitation to explain the behavior of all material bodies — not only on the Earth but also in outer space — in terms of material particles (mass) and force.

As telescopes improved and astronomers learned more about other planets and the stars, it became clear that the Earth — in spatial terms — is only an infinitesimal part of the universe. It is not surprising, then, that scientists now tend to regard the universe as the most general manifestation of natural laws, and life on Earth as a special case. In particular, most modern biologists tend to analyze living things as special cases (albeit very complex ones) of general laws that describe all phenomena in terms of material particles and forces.

Copernicus.jpg

Copernicus, De revolutionibus orbium coelestium (1543)

This mechanistic approach to living things fits well with Ren� Descartes’s 17th-century "machine metaphor," according to which animal bodies are machines composed of smaller machines. This metaphor still dominates much of modern biology. In 1998 Bruce Alberts, President of the U.S. National Academy of Sciences, wrote in the prestigious journal Cell that "the entire cell can be viewed as a factory that contains an elaborate network of interlocking assembly lines, each of which is composed of a set of large protein machines." The same issue of Cell carried articles about "chromatin-modifying machines," "chaperone machines," and "machines within machines." One article was titled "Mechanical Devices of the Spliceosome: Motors, Clocks, Springs, and Things."

Darwin and Design

In addition to working within the framework of the machine metaphor, most biologists also work within the materialistic framework of Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution. According to Darwin, all living things are descendants of one or a few common ancestors that have been modified by unguided processes such as variations and natural selection. Adaptations that previous biologists had attributed to design, Darwin argued, were actually produced by natural selection, which operates without foresight or purpose. In 2007, Francisco Ayala wrote that "Darwin’s greatest contribution to science" was "to explain the design of organisms, their complexity, diversity, and marvelous contrivances, as the result of natural processes," without the need for intelligence.

But Darwin did not know the mechanism of heredity or the origin of novel variations, so his theory was seriously incomplete. After 1900, Mendelian genetics seemed to remedy the first deficiency, and after 1953 DNA mutations seemed to remedy the second. The resulting Modern Synthesis combined Darwin’s theory with the idea that organismal development is controlled by a genetic program written in DNA sequences, and that DNA mutations can change the program to generate the raw materials of evolution. According to molecular biologist Jacques Monod, "with that, and the understanding of the random physical basis of mutation that molecular biology has also provided, the mechanism of Darwinism is at last securely founded. And man has to understand that he is a mere accident." (Quoted in Horace Freeland Judson’s 1979 book, The Eighth Day of Creation, p. 217.)

So in the context of Darwinian evolution and molecular biology, many biologists tend to regard the living organism as a special kind of machine — that is, a computer, in which DNA sequences are the software. As Bill Gates put it in 1995, "DNA is like a computer program but far, far more advanced than any software ever created." In both the technical and popular literature, phrases such as "genetic program" and "DNA blueprint" have become commonplace. Francis Collins, Director of the Human Genome Project, wrote in his 2006 book The Language of God that DNA is an "amazing script, carrying within it all of the instructions for building a human being." (p. 2)

Yet combining Darwinian evolution with the notion of a genetic program leads to a paradox. Computers and computer programs (like machines in general) are made by intelligent agents, namely, human beings. Not surprisingly, proponents of intelligent design (ID) have argued that machine- and code-like aspects of living things point to the very design that Darwinian evolution tries to exclude. Thus Michael Behe points to a molecular machine, the bacterial flagellum, which does not function unless several dozen parts are already in place — a feature characteristic of intelligent design. And Stephen Meyer points to complex and highly specified DNA sequences, which like computer software cannot arise by chance but point to an intelligent designer.

According to pro-evolution philosophers Massimo Pigliucci and Maarten Boudry, "creationists and their modern heirs of the Intelligent Design movement have been eager to exploit mechanical metaphors for their own purposes." So "if we want to keep Intelligent Design out of the classroom, not only do we have to exclude the ‘theory’ from the biology curriculum, but we also have to be weary [sic] of using scientific metaphors that bolster design-like misconceptions about living systems." Pigliucci and Boudry conclude that since "machine/information metaphors have been grist to the mill of ID creationism, fostering design intuitions and other misconceptions about living systems, we think it is time to dispense with them altogether."

But there are better reasons to dispense with the machine metaphor (and Pigliucci and Boudry mention some). Although the mechanistic approach has borne some fruit in biological research, the truth is that living things are very different from machines.

The End of the Machine Metaphor

A century after Newton’s mechanical picture of the universe captured the scientific imagination, philosopher Immanuel Kant pointed out that living things — which he called "organized beings" — cannot be understood mechanistically. A machine is organized from the outside in by an external agent, but a living thing organizes itself from the inside out. "An organized being is then not a mere machine, for that has merely moving power, but it possesses in itself formative power of a self-propagating kind which it communicates to its materials though they have it not of themselves; it organizes them." So organisms cannot be understood by analogy to any natural causality we know. Instead, we must conceive of them as having an "internal purposiveness." In an organized being, "every part is reciprocally end and means. In it nothing is vain, without purpose, or to be ascribed to a blind mechanism of nature." (�65, �66)

According to Kant, the idea that organisms are internally purposive is a "regulative principle" that governs our thinking. In order to understand organisms properly, we cannot help but think of them in terms of purpose and design (and modern biologists, in spite of Darwin, habitually talk about organisms in such terms). But Kant did not claim that his description applied to the actual "thing in itself," which for him was unknowable — a philosophical position that has been influential but controversial. The important point here is that he recognized that organisms cannot be understood as machines.

There is now growing criticism of the machine metaphor among biologists and philosophers of biology. According to Keith Baverstock, "a rapidly accruing body of evidence challenges the DNA centric dogmas that dominate evolution and cell regulation, both of which are predicated on the machine metaphor." Daniel Nicholson writes that "despite some interesting similarities, organisms and machines are fundamentally different kinds of systems… the former are intrinsically purposive whereas the latter are extrinsically purposive." Thus the machine metaphor "fails to provide an appropriate theoretical understanding of what living systems are." According to Ann Gauger, "the machine metaphor fails," in part, because organisms are "causally circular beings." Not only do new cells require existing cells, but also in many cases the biosynthetic pathway of a molecule requires the very molecule that is being synthesized. Stephen Talbott bluntly calls biology’s refusal to disown the machine metaphor "an inexcusable mistake" that "has gripped the scientific community for decades, severely perverting biological understanding."

Yet going beyond a mechanistic approach to living things will not be easy. After all, the world of Newtonian mechanics seems so… well, natural. But just as relativity and quantum physics demonstrated that Newtonian mechanics is a special case from the cosmic and atomic perspectives, so a revolution in biology is now demonstrating that Newtonian mechanics is a special case from the organismal perspective as well. All three revolutions reveal that Newton’s laws are only a subset of the laws governing phenomena in nature, which is much richer (and stranger) than is dreamt of in a mechanistic approach.

Revolutionary Biology

To overcome the limitations of the mechanistic approach to living things, Nicolas Rashevsky developed what he called "relational biology" in the 1950s. Instead of starting by analyzing the molecular constituents of a cell, Rashevsky focused on the organization of relations in a cell. Rashevsky’s student Robert Rosen developed relational biology with the help of "category theory," a mathematical approach introduced in the 1940s by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders MacLane. Relational biology has been further developed by Ion Baianu, Andr�e Ehresmann and Jean-Paul Vanbremeersch, Paul Kainen, Aloisius Louie, and Richard Sternberg.

According to Rosen, relational biology is revolutionary because it describes living things in terms of laws that are not found in the inanimate universe. No longer is the organism a special case of universal natural laws; instead, the organism is the general case and the inanimate universe is a special case, because the latter embodies only a subset of the laws that apply in living things. As Rosen put it:

Organisms, far from being a special case, an embodiment of more general principles or laws we believe we already know, are indications that these laws themselves are profoundly incomplete. The universe described by these laws is an extremely impoverished, nongeneric one… In short, far from being a special case of these laws, and reducible to them, biology provides the most spectacular examples of their inadequacy. The alternative is… a more generic view of the scientific world itself, in which it is the mechanistic laws that are the special cases. [Essays on Life Itself, pp. 33-34]

Does this mean that we now understand life? Of course not, any more than we understood the universe after 1543. But the radical change in perspective provided by relational biology — like the change in perspective provided by Copernicus — at least opens the door to more fruitful exploration.

Where does this leave intelligent design? Alive and well.

In his just-published book Being As Communion: A Metaphysics of Information, William Dembski defines intelligent design as "the study of patterns (hence ‘design’) in nature that give empirical evidence of resulting from teleology (hence ‘intelligent’)." (p. 58) But this definition does not limit ID to tracing teleology back to an external agent.

For Aristotle, "design" meant "a principle of movement in something other than the thing moved," while "nature" meant "a principle in the thing itself." But for Aristotle the "principle" in each case was teleological, so he was distinguishing between external and internal teleology. Materialism strips nature of internal teleology and treats organisms as machines, leaving only external teleology. For Dembski, ID is not limited to external teleology, but (like Aristotle’s metaphysics) encompasses internal teleology as well. When ID advocates look at life mechanistically, they do so "as a temporary measure, as part of a reductio ad absurdum argument, to refute materialism. Once materialism is refuted, however, intelligent design is able to leave a mechanistic understanding of life behind, looking at life as it is." (p. 62)

And for Dembski, life — indeed, the entire cosmos — is fundamentally informational. He defines information as realizing some possibilities by ruling out others. Since matter only exists in the form of material objects — that is, as particular realizations out of many possibilities — information is ontologically prior to matter. Thus "information should properly be regarded as the prime entity and object of science, displacing matter from its current position of eminence… Materialists see the natural world as matter all the way down. Information realists, like me, see the natural world as information all the way down." (p. 91)

What is the source of the information in nature? Darwinian evolution attributes it to natural selection, but Dembski demonstrates that natural selection is really "an information redistributor rather than an information generator or creator … On materialist principles, intelligence is not real but an epiphenomenon of underlying material processes. But if intelligence is real and has inherent causal powers, it can do more than merely redistribute information — it can also create it." (p. 185) Indeed, "the defining property of intelligence is its ability to create information," and "intelligence is the ultimate source of information." (pp. 186, 187)

Furthermore, Dembski writes, "Because information is produced as some possibilities are realized to the exclusion of others, information is fundamentally relational: the possibilities associated with information exist only in relation to other possibilities." (p. 29) Thus "informational realism… is a relational ontology." (p. 197) Like relational biology, informational realism regards relations among objects as more fundamental than the objects themselves.

Informational realism and relational biology, unlike the machine metaphor and materialistic evolution, can conceptualize organisms as they really are. Instead of evolutionary biology, we now have revolutionary biology.

Photo credit: Anders Sandberg/Flickr.

Jonathan Wells

Senior Fellow, Center for Science and Culture
Jonathan Wells has received two Ph.D.s, one in Molecular and Cell Biology from the University of California at Berkeley, and one in Religious Studies from Yale University. A Senior Fellow at Discovery Institute's Center for Science and Culture, he has previously worked as a postdoctoral research biologist at the University of California at Berkeley and the supervisor of a medical laboratory in Fairfield, California. He also taught biology at California State University in Hayward and continues to lecture on the subject.

Share

Tags

PhilosophyScience